It is a reasonable view that powers not expressly given to the government are denied it, in the US constitution, even apart from the flat assertion of that notion in the 10th Amendment.
But in that case the stipulations of the powers of congress,
for instance, in Article I Section 8 and elsewhere ought to have been
sufficient.
Whence the need, then, for the express denials of power in Section 9 and elsewhere?
To make assurance doubly sure against the temptation to
refuse to understand?
To ensure the denied powers were not misconstrued as
separately contained and hence affirmed in the inherent nature of the legislative
power attributed to the congress at Section 1 of Article I?
And in that case do conditional or partial denials imply
powers only limited or partly denied?
Are there un-enumerated
powers inherent in the nature of legislative power, itself, that, so to speak, “go
without saying”?
Much reliance has been traditionally placed on the powers
allegedly inherent in the executive power vested in the president by Article
II, Section 1, so little being actually said about what his job is.
And the same is true of the judicial power attributed to the
supreme and other federal courts in Article III, Section 1.
But that way lies an ocean of invisible ink, alleged mind-reading
of those long dead, and insertion into the constitution and government of what
the reader himself thinks necessary, inevitable, unavoidable, or merely a very good
idea.
On the other hand, perhaps too much has been made of this
approach by the “limited government” side.
Perhaps the point of the affirmations of power was not to
provide a complete list, making safe and valid the idea if a power was not
affirmed then it does not exist and has not been granted to the congress, the
president, or whomever.
Perhaps those who talk in terms of inherent powers are
really right, and the point of the affirmations is to make specific denials
impossible, while the point of the denials is to make specific affirmations impossible.
So, again, could it be the men of the convention and of
their time took it for granted that of
course there were powers that were inherent in the executive, legislative,
and judicial powers and “went without saying”?
Often remarks before, during, and after the convention made
by men at Philadelphia or in the ratifying conventions or engaged in the
political battle wrote exactly as though they thought so.
And if they are right then Article 10 subtracts nothing from
these powers since they are in fact attributed to the branches of the general
government as inherent in the nature of the executive, legislative, or judicial
powers.
Well, there is this to give the fan of inherent powers pause.
Well, there is this to give the fan of inherent powers pause.
The powers of a national government not federative in
character are quite different from those of a national government claiming to
live only by powers conceded of necessity by a group of states too small and
weak to do well in their separated and jarring sovereignties.
At the convention, several men spoke out, in fact, for
abolishing the states or making a national government strong enough to simply
overwhelm their pretentions to independence and residual sovereignty.
In their eyes, the national government should be
omnicompetent, leaving for regional or provincial governments only delegated,
revocable, and overridable authority to deal with local matters and matters too
insignificant for the national government to wish to deal with, itself.
In fact, on some occasions during and after the ratification
struggle, Hamilton variously espoused the views that the federal government
crafted in Philadelphia did or should stand in such a relationship to the
states.
But he and other such extreme nationalists were a minority
before, at, and after the convention.
Madison, himself a less extreme nationalist, was certainly
himself for a strong central government, and his proposals that representation
in both houses be proportional to
population and that the federal legislature be empowered to review and nullify
state legislation before it could take effect were both rejected.
As was the suggestion of others (not Madison) that senators
be popularly elected from districts of equal population whose boundaries might
be drawn across state lines, and drawn so large that some of them might
encompass not only entire smaller states but parts of neighboring states.
That, too, was a non-starter.
Part of the point of these suggestions, as was very well
understood by those present, even in the mind of Madison who would later, to a
degree, join Jefferson on the other side, was to end state pretentions to
sovereignty and give the lie to any notion that the new government was a mere
creature of a compact among states, their creation and their servant.
But discussion of invention of such a strong national
government to replace not only the Articles of Confederation but the union as
previously understood, the union as a confederation of states retaining their separate
identities, independence, and sovereignty provoked a reaction.
At the opposite pole there were those in attendance who were
jealous of the prerogatives and powers of the states that sent them to Philadelphia,
and disposed more to rectify than to replace the Articles of Confederation.
Remember the New Jersey Plan.
And remember as well the weakness of the plural executive it
proposed.
As I said, the nationalism of not only Hamilton but even the
likes of Madison was in fact rejected by the convention, both on its own
account and because the conventioneers were unwilling to accept a final
proposal without unanimous support from the state delegations.
Or, despite Madison’s bold talk, one that might be ultimately
ratified by the small states only because they faced the frightening prospect
of being left out of a new union comprising all the larger and more powerful ones.
In the end, the Great Compromise produced a kind of hybrid
between the two, more national than the Articles of Confederation but still far
more merely federal than the indisputably sovereign central government wanted
and dreamed of by Hamilton then and later and Madison then, but later not so
much.
Bearing all that in mind, I think we are forced to be wary
of assertions of powers based only on bluster about inherent powers and appeals
to invisible ink.
No comments:
Post a Comment